Icebutik
  • Home
  • World
  • Anomalies
  • Unexplained
  • Phenomena
  • Weird
  • Odd News
  • Mysteries
  • Contact us
Facebook Twitter Instagram
Icebutik
  • Home
  • World

    Halt Israel legal reform, urges defence minister

    March 25, 2023

    The Indonesian power ranger — Global Issues

    March 25, 2023

    Myanmar’s military jet fuel supplies hit by latest US sanctions | Conflict News

    March 25, 2023

    France protests: Macron takes off 'luxury' watch during TV interview

    March 24, 2023

    Challenges & Prospects for Peace & Human Security — Global Issues

    March 24, 2023
  • Anomalies
  • Unexplained
  • Phenomena
  • Weird
  • Odd News
  • Mysteries
  • Contact us
Icebutik
Home»Anomalies»Transcendental Skepticism
Anomalies

Transcendental Skepticism

SteinarBy SteinarMay 10, 2022No Comments22 Mins Read
Facebook Twitter Pinterest LinkedIn Tumblr WhatsApp VKontakte Email
Share
Facebook Twitter LinkedIn Pinterest Email


Truth, when it comes down to it (and despite what we might want to say in a fit of heady principled grandstanding—in debate, for example) is nothing but a negotiation, an endless experimentation, a
trial in which our practices and beliefs get tested against the spontaneity of things
themselves, things clothed for a moment in our notions of them. Removing ourselves, then, from any self-serving notions of truth
 leaves us in a place of radical openness, the place of “the question” in which the poet Rilke enjoined us to live. Such a standpoint of radical openness (of honest questioning) suggests that it is skepticism, too, from which we must withdraw—to have the fortitude to even, at times, be
skeptical of our sometime skepticism. Shouldn
’t we be absolutely vigilant that our skepticism (perhaps through habit) won’t transform from method to position, from means to end? But my intention here is not to wax poetic or unduly subtle about truth. Rather, my aim is more practical, if at the same time it is philosophical: to examine the limits of skepticism, and to ask at just what point does skepticism end, and, when it does (surely it must?), what comes after skepticism…

For the video I mention above, do we have a
sense of how credible the footage is? My first impression is that of course it isn’t
—that it’s either a click-batey hoax, or worse: a video clipped out of context
and made to
appear to be just what the producer, looking for mere views, wants
us to think it is, which is a compelling video of a mysteriously-shaped UFO caught on
camera by an airline pilot. After submitting the video to a more serious-minded
group of UFO researchers and enthusiasts, their initial and very preliminary
assessment was rather sober-minded and fair: if it is at all an actual object
in space (the suggestion: perhaps a balloon of some kind?), then its rapid
motion is likely largely apparent: a parallaxic effect, not a consequence of a
mysterious propulsion system. But this is likely too generous: the video is of a sort that is rather easily faked (just take a look at this website which complies numerous faked or falsified videos). Still, taking such a skeptical position against the view
that this is a “true” UFO (an object, that is, which definitely
cannot
be explained by means of conventional or common-sensical premises—something we must, of course, interrogate carefully) is surely a sound one to take,
especially when all that we have here is but one random and unanalyzed video.
We know little to nothing of its provenance. We know little to nothing of the
context within which it was produced. We don’t even really know (without further investigation) 
who produced
this video 
(so far as credibility of the source or witness is a factor to consider: it is surely possible that some good evidence comes from bad sources). In other words, this particular video has little to no evidential value as far as the UFO phenomenon itself is concerned. It is an occasion, rather, to
practice intellectual restraint, to allow skepticism to rightfully make its
appearance in the name of truth. But what this (most likely falsified or even
faked) video does also demonstrate is a curious gap in, or failing of, the very
skepticism that, in this case, saves us from too much worry. (Though in the
spirit of absolute honesty, due diligence requires a rigorous follow-up on both
the provenance and content of this video, implying that something approaching a
final judgment must await this more complete analysis.)

Let’s talk
strategy for a moment. How are we to demonstrate that this video ought to be
dismissed as a fake, forgery, hoax, or falsification? There are a number of
analytical techniques open to the investigator, and here I do not wish to
review them (this is an exercise best left to experts). What I’d rather like to
look at is simply the strategy of refutation itself—its basic logic. There
would seem to be three options to the skeptic.

In the first place, one can look at the relevant content
of the video (in this case, the allegedly anomalous flying object) and try (with
various analytical methods) to determine whether that content was inserted
into the video—whether the relevant bits of
the video are out of context, foreign intruders into an otherwise
ordinary video. 
Certain visual anomalies or irregularities in the image (possibly found in the image data itself) might indicate such an interpretation. Here we would be accepting the general veracity of everything about the video except its anomalous content: something that wasn’t native to the video was put in after the fact, making it a fake video because of that illicit intrusion. In the second place, the skeptical investigator might try to determine whether some or all of the native content itself was altered
in some illicit way, yielding precisely what the author of the video wants you
to believe about it: that there was a genuine UFO caught on camera for you to
marvel at. Here, nothing foreign to the content of the video was inserted; rather, it was 
the native content itself that was changed. Failing this, the skeptic’s last recourse would be to accept the
footage as is, but simply dispute the UFO
interpretation of the relevant content (content which is in itself truthful).

All attempts at the refutation of UFO claims based on video- or
photographic evidence are versions of one of these strategies. And of course, there
is nothing wrong with any of this in principle—surely there will be cases where
it is straightforwardly true that the video was either altered, contains
falsified content within an otherwise authentic video or photo, is an outright fabrication (using the right software for manipulation or creative purposes), or records something perhaps easily mistaken for a UFO but which is, upon closer analysis, identifiable
. But equally surely there will be videos (or photographs) of an
allegedly anomalous sort that cannot be so straightforwardly refuted as being
hoaxed, faked, falsified or misinterpreted. Indeed, there may be videos whose content does not lend itself to any conventional explanation.

Or are there?

This is the crucial point: to what
extent is the skeptic amenable to the existence of genuinely anomalous content … indeed, to genuine anomalies period? Is there ever a point at which
skepticism is overcome, and we move beyond it to the more disorienting position
of having to actually encounter the anomalous as anomalous, but yet
still without the conviction of a true (or even just merely adequate)
understanding of it? What comes after skepticism—and what
allows us to get there?

Let us focus for
a moment on a video that, by all accounts, is authentically anomalous. It contains what both pilots and now (after the June 2021 watershed Pentagon
report) even the US military openly acknowledges is footage of an unidentified
aerial phenomenon: the so-called “
Gimbal” video. At first glance, it is not particularly anomalous,
as the object appears to just hover and, according to one of the pilots,
“rotate”. But when you consider that this was something seen by pilots as they
flew their jets at cruising speed, at altitude, and with headwinds of over a
hundred knots, it quickly becomes puzzling as to how this object is able to
both keep pace with the jets and rotate seemingly effortlessly against the strong
winds. What exactly are we looking at, then?

No object with
this kind of (apparently closed) geometry can maintain the altitude, forward
velocity and rotational oscillations in which it is observed to engage—no
human-fashioned technology, in any case. What is the object’s source of lift?
Of propulsion and rotational movement? A balloon (or something like it) would
have to move with the wind, and could not maintain a stable rotational axis and rotate without some internal means of propulsion, let alone keep pace with
the pilots filming it. In other words, assuming that the video is veridical,
this is a genuinely unidentified flying object (or “aerial phenomenon” as the preferred phrase has it). Thus, the skeptic must question: is the video
veridical—is it of an objectively “real” object flying out in the space near where
the pilots were flying? Or, even if it is veridical, perhaps the pilots
themselves have mistaken some other phenomenon for something unidentified—that
is, perhaps both our interpretation of the content of the video, and the
pilot’s own interpretation of what they thought they were filming, is wrong.

Is the video
itself veridical? Perhaps it is not. Perhaps it was faked—but in this case, it
would have to have been faked by the military, who’ve admitted it is a video of
something they can’t explain. We would then wonder why … and here all manner of
theories (many of which being conspiracy-oriented) are ready-at-hand in order
to flesh out this more sinister possibility. But what those strategies that
focus only on the (internal) content of the video lack is a full
accounting of the alleged encounter, which would have to reckon with the experiences of those who were supposed to have filmed the object. A
video or photograph is generally (but not always) taken by someone who is also actively
seeing the object directly, without the mediation of the camera or video
equipment; surely this also counts as evidence of the truthfulness of the
footage captured. So, as part of an authentically skeptical investigation of video or
photographic UFO evidence one must also interview the witnesses taking the footage. In
this particular case (documented here),
if we want to argue that the footage was faked, then we also have to impugn the
pilots’
own eye-witness accounts
. We’d have to either argue that there was a conspiracy involving the
(military) witnesses and military officials (including the Pentagon, which has admitted to the veracity of this video and others like it) to concoct and release a faked
video. But to what end? What would be the motivation, especially if the US is itself actively admitting it can’t explain what was filmed (and tracked)? We are then
down the rabbit hole of interrogating the complexities of US military and government informational secrecy.

Surely such a line
of inquiry is possible; but is this the most likely explanation for what
’s going on here? Is it
even the best? Without further, more concrete and specific evidence to suggest a kind of
government-military fabrication
in this particular case, this sort of
explanation has to remain speculative. It would not be enough to reason
purely
inductively
, by, for example, noting prior government-military fabrications of this sort.
It has to be shown that
this particular case is most likely part of a more general
pattern in play. In other words: since it is always possible to reason that anything coming from government/military channels that looks out of the ordinary is a signal of (purposeful) dissimulation, such an explanation would bear the burden of having to first show why this kind of a scenario, in this particular case, is plausible.

So where does this
leave us? It leaves us with footage that we seem to have to accept as veridical, and with
eyewitness testimony that we also have to assume is trustworthy. Thus, the only
recourse the skeptic would have in this case is to challenge the interpretation
of what is was that the eyewitnesses actually saw (or came to think that they saw), and which was also captured on video for us to see.
In order to do this, one has to come up with at least some plausible, but
conventional, interpretation. The hard question in this case is: Can we do it?

Remember, the
skeptic cannot just challenge the videographic content itself, because in this
case we’re assuming there was a there there, so to speak: there was an
object visible both to the (infrared) camera the pilots used in filming, and to
their unaided eyes. In this way we finally arrive at the main task of the skeptic: to
produce an adequate explanation in conventional terms of what was actually seen
and recorded on video. And of course, out there on the blogosphere, we find just that: Mick West, self-described debunker, thinks he has the explanation
—not just for the video we consider here, but for almost all of the leaked or declassified Navy videos released to date (quite an ambitious wish list for any debunker). The particular form that his explanation takes is rather common in the world of debunkerism. It assumes, naturally, that these videos contain veridical content—that they capture real objects really witnessed by the pilots or military officers who filmed them. (To doubt this would be to stretch the credibility of the skeptic, as we have already suggested.) But it then goes on to argue that we are witnessing either artifacts of the filming equipment (in which case we are owed an explanation as to why that the pilots claim to have actually seen something with their unaided eyes); ordinary planes strangely illuminated (another artifact of the filming equipment?) or blurred from distance; or a balloon. (One can read a synopsis of many of West’s explanations here.)

The method of demonstrating the likelihood of many of these explanations West offers is quite curious, if not also rather common among debunkers: he shows that ordinary objects, when given the right conditions and filmed with the equipment originally used, can be made to resemble the seemingly anomalous content of the videos in question. (We might call this an argument from simulation or resemblance: argumentum ex simulatione.) But again, in this particular case, content analysis simply cannot suffice on its own: we cannot simply impugn the content of the videos alone, since we also have witness testimony corroborating it. Tellingly, West at one point admits he doesn’t really know what the pilots saw, so he doesn’t (and indeed cannot) offer us an explanation of what they say they saw. At which point we must remain deeply skeptical of this debunkerism, and wonder if the skepticism is a priori…that his skeptical conclusions are driving his debunking arguments. And of course, this is all done, he seems to think, to quash the aliens are here! frenzy the videos seemed to have caused on the ’Net when they dropped some years ago. (So I guess now we know what’s really driving the skepticism: the question-begging assumption that aliens can’t be visiting, so it can’t be alien/non-human technology, which means it must be human technology. In other words: it can’t be, so it isn’t!)

There are, then, only two real possibilities left to us—again
assuming that there was an actual object with the kinematical profile on
display: either (1) it was a structured craft of some technological sort (this is what it appears to us to be
—although the skeptic must be wary of appearances); or (2) it is a natural phenomenon (possibly of a kind unknown to science). Now, for absolute logical completeness we must, of course, countenance at least another, third, possibility, which is the one favored by, for example, Jacques Vallée: (3) that the apparently structured craft we observe is itself part of an intelligent meta-system and should therefore be interpreted semiotically or symbolically, rather than strictly physically. Curiously, the claim here is that we look beyond the ordinary appearance of a physical object, and try to contextualize the perception with a theory, as we might do as we stare down into the eerie blue glow of a nuclear reactor: what we see is a blue haze, but we are told that what we are seeing is a secondary effect of the radiation produced in the core (the so-called Cherenkov radiation). This is an interesting speculative suggestion (one considered briefly here) which, while meriting much further discussion, we must largely pass over in silence. (We will have occasion in a future post to examine this possibility more closely, and more carefully.)

So, can the object in the video be
technological?

It is surely possible
that some kind of a technology is on display in this video. But the problem is that if it is a technology, it quickly becomes obvious it could not be any known technology, for the mystery is not
just how it could be hovering where it was seen, but how it could also actively
move, rotate and keep pace with pilots and yet display no obvious means of propulsion. (If you don
’t find this convincing, and prefer Mick West’s more comforting skeptical safety, you must, again, explain what Ryan Graves and other pilots say they saw with their own eyes: what they saw, sometimes at very close range, really can’t be described as conventional aircraft or balloons—at least not in every case.) So, perhaps there is an unknown technology of some kind which
someone besides the US has managed to build? (Graves himself seems to accept this is as a possibility for at least some of what he saw.) If that is true, then it
would be news to the entire science community, and we’d have a new
problem: how could such impressive and incredible technology have been kept
secret for so long
? (One must also consider that objects with similar flight characteristics have been noted in UFO reports for decades, from even before the invention of the jet engine.) Yet, this isn’t even the most difficult problem. The more
difficult problem here is that, even if we are able to find an existing theory of
physics that can explain this kind of a flight profile (and the going belief among many in the UFO community is that it must involve general relativistic physics, with something like a warp drive), any
conceivable technology based on it would seem to be hundreds, if not thousands
of years in the future. No one knows how it could even be built (although some think they know what physics could be employed), and it
’s hard to believe that some one country (or maybe a small and secretive alliance of nations) could have developed a technology that, given what we do know, would seem to be centuries or millennia away. If this is advanced technology, it can’t be ours. Which is to say: it can’t be human technology.

So, it seems we
must eliminate the human technological possibility, leaving only two
remaining options: that it is a perfectly natural phenomenon (perhaps a rare
one, or even a new one heretofore unknown to science)—or it is a kind of
non-human technological object of unknown nature or origin. Let us consider each in turn, as we bring our reflections on ufological skepticism to a close…

Is it a natural phenomenon?

Surely the
concept ‘natural’ is a tricky, perhaps slippery and loaded concept. And maybe
it doesn
’t always mean what we think—or want it to mean. Perhaps
we must nuance, or in any case revisit the concept ‘natural’ in new and
interesting ways in order that it may plausibly apply to the anomalous content of the video in question. Would this not be some kind of progress, even if we are no closer to a satisfactory understanding of the (UAP) phenomenon? In any case, f
or the moment let us simply take ‘natural’ to be a word that sets up an opposition, as in “the
forces of blind nature” 
as opposed to “the deliberate choices
of an intelligent being”. I am surely part of nature (I am a natural being),
but I am capable, as well, of deliberate choices in ways that, say, other
things are not. Though I am subject to the forces of nature, as creature of it I also experience myself as having choices, and indeed can make and act on them
(whether I am “really” free or not doesn’t matter here, as William James, and
even Kant before him had realized: we act 
as though we are). A
quintessentially “natural” phenomenon like a thunderstorm, for example, doesn’t
seem to act from deliberate choice—or to deliberate at all. Rather, as with all
‘natural’ forces or events, it is simply 
there, and does its thing.
It is a blind object, subject 
only to the laws of nature. It
doesn’t react or respond, say, to me or my presence. Or, if it does, then it
does so in a mostly indifferent way. Living things are precisely
different: they are reactive and responsive in ways that thunderstorms,
earthquakes, solar flares (etc.) are not. Beyond this, there is
intelligent
life—‘intelligence’, again, being yet another slippery, loaded concept.
Thunderstorms are powerful, involving great forces of nature (on Earth), but in
themselves they are not intelligent, like octopi or dolphins (or even
lobsters). The anomalous objects witnessed by the pilots who took that “Gimbal”
video seem to behave in very deliberate ways (moving against the wind, in very
strong prevailing winds that would require some technological assistance in
order to counter), and it’s this deliberateness that suggests 
intelligence behind
the object, of a sort that would place it outside of the domain of the purely “natural”.
And intelligence suggests 
consciousness of some form. In other
words, this object (and the many others on record that are like it), if it is
not a natural object (a production of blind nature, like a thunderstorm), is
really, then, a cypher for an intelligence (and therefore a consciousness) of
which we have no real understanding beyond the appearances we are able to
capture on video, on radar, or recall in memory. And if we want to insist on
the “natural” hypothesis (that this is a new phenomenon of nature heretofore unknown
to science), then we must, indeed, revisit and radically critique our
(conventional) notion of ‘nature’ (and its opposition to intelligence) in order
to arrive at a sufficiently robust concept of nature that can accommodate such seemingly intelligent phenomena. We would have to enlarge our concept of ‘nature’ to give it intelligence, or enlarge our concept of ‘intelligence’ to make the natural
world an expression of it. We
could go in this direction, but would we want to? Does this have anything to do with this particular case, or are we just applying something we already might like to believe to something about which we have no real understanding—putting the phenomena in service to our favorite concepts or theories, and thus potentially missing what is truly anomalous about the phenomena?

So, we seem to be left with only the technological thesis itself. We must, therefore, be careful to state it correctly, to understand clearly
what it is we are saying, and what it is we are not saying.
We should appreciate that we are attempting to characterize our
ignorance of what the object is
 in some very definite, even concrete way, by positioning it partly within the realm of the familiar (by calling it 
‘technological’) and partly outside of the realm of the familiar, by fully recognizing that, even though it appears technological, it is of a sort whose nature and origin is still, nonetheless, vexatious. We state this without
admitting any specific hypothesis beyond what is most reasonable as a working interpretative assumption (which, again, will require us to put the shovel down 
somewhere:
‘reasonable’ is relative). We are asserting that it: exists; is “technological”
(that is, a seemingly deliberately 
fashioned object from the resources available to an intelligent
being); and is inexplicable (for we possess no clear or readily available
understanding of how such a technology could be created, or who could have created it). It is on this basis that we assert that it is, therefore, 
anomalous to any number of relevant theoretical disciplines.

This admission of definite and
specific ignorance, even while partly contextualizing the phenomenon within the realm of the familiar, is, then, the stage after the wholly justifiable
skepticism that must at first be pursued. A
fter
skepticism, there is very specific ignorance: here is a thing which we can partly grasp, but which, even so, remains enigmatic for very specific reasons
—reasons that have to do with what it is we think we already understood about things in the world, but which this object is forcing us to critically reexamine. There is here, to repeat, no belief or acceptance of anything more than our actual
ignorance,
an acknowledgment (after working through the possibilities) of a now known unknown. It is the actual ignorance itself—our
decisive and definite
inability to account for the anomalous while accepting nonetheless its reality as something appearing in some specific way to us—that is the first
stage of authentic knowledge.

⧫⧫

At the end of the day, we who would be skeptics for a time must ask (and this is the Socratic question par excellence): Am I skeptical of something
because it is of a sort that merits doubt, or am I doubtful of it just because
I’m skeptical?
After the conviction of many instances in which one’s
skepticism is confirmed, one is tempted to generalize, and make the inductive
leap: this, too, must also be a hoax, falsification, or fake. Here skepticism takes
over and becomes primary—an end rather than a mere means. Thus is it hard to
tell what grounds one’s doubt: the conviction of skepticism alone, or the
doubtfulness of the thing itself. 
One must see this skepticism turned recalcitrant as pathological, not philosophical.

The true test of
the UFO skeptic comes not in the many cases that fall to the skeptic’s attack,
but in the few that don’t—or rather, from the mere
acknowledgment that these few even exist
. Otherwise, we would seem to be dealing with dogmatic (and pathological) skepticism. 
Underlying it is a kind of faith: that this, too, shall be explained—that every inexplicable UFO encounter or sighting or evidence will eventually fall to existing science (or common-sense). It is born of the conviction that, to use J. Allen Hynek’s way of putting it, “it can’t be true, so it isn’t”—thus inverting the most basic axiom of modal logic (that actuality implies possibility). But what the dogmatic skeptic cannot see is that, eventually, it is science itself that must change to accommodate the anomalous. If it didn’t, or couldn’t, it wouldn’t be science. It would be dogmatism.



Source link

Related

Share. Facebook Twitter Pinterest LinkedIn Tumblr WhatsApp Email
Previous ArticleOpacity Surrounds Fossil Fuels in Mexico — Global Issues
Next Article Abortion protests at justices’ homes fuel a new round of recriminations
Steinar
  • Website
  • Facebook
  • Pinterest

Related Posts

Aliens could be found in dust, scientists say

March 25, 2023

In Your Face – Life in Jonestown

March 25, 2023

Sámi Hauntings and Resisting Colonization

March 24, 2023

New study investigates the impact of the COVID-19 pandemic on UFO reporting

March 24, 2023

Leave A Reply Cancel Reply

Categories
  • Anomalies (1,078)
  • Icebutik Store (271)
  • Odd News (1,714)
  • Unexplained-mysteries (856)
  • Unexplained-phenomena (1,728)
  • Weird (10)
  • World (1,534)

Subscribe to Updates

Get the latest creative news from FooBar about art, design and business.

Loading
Latest Posts

This is Sparta: Fierce Warriors of the Ancient World (Video)

March 26, 2023

Florida Atlantic continues Cinderella run, clinches Final Four berth in instant classic over Kansas State

March 26, 2023

Did Nero Really Fiddle While Rome Burned?

March 26, 2023
  • About us
  • Contact us
  • Privacy Policy
  • Terms of use
© 2023 Designed by icebutik

Type above and press Enter to search. Press Esc to cancel.